Skip to content

Commit

Permalink
Lectures 23
Browse files Browse the repository at this point in the history
  • Loading branch information
zeramorphic committed Feb 19, 2024
1 parent 342794f commit 987b2fe
Showing 1 changed file with 110 additions and 0 deletions.
110 changes: 110 additions & 0 deletions iii/lc/02_measurable_cardinals.tex
Original file line number Diff line number Diff line change
Expand Up @@ -423,3 +423,113 @@ \subsection{Reflection}
In particular,
\[ \mathsf{ZFC} + \mathsf{IC} <_{\Con} \mathsf{ZFC} + \mathsf{WCC} \]
Note that in the proof that strongly compact cardinals are measurable, we used a language with \( 2^\kappa \)-many symbols.

\subsection{Ultrapowers of the universe}
In order to avoid proper classes, we will consider ultrapowers of particular set universes.
Later, we will briefly explain how all of this could have been done in a proper class universe such as \( \mathrm{V} \).
For convenience, we will assume that \( \kappa < \lambda \) where \( \kappa \) is measurable and \( \lambda \) is inaccessible, so \( \mathrm{V}_\lambda \vDash \mathsf{ZFC} + \mathsf{MC} \).
We will take the ultrapower of \( \mathrm{V}_\lambda \).

Let \( U \) be a \( \kappa \)-complete nonprincipal ultrafilter on \( \kappa \), and form the ultrapower of \( \mathrm{V}_\lambda \), consisting of equivalence classes of functions \( f : \kappa \to \mathrm{V}_\lambda \) where \( f \sim g \) when \( \qty{\alpha \mid f(\alpha) = g(\alpha)} \in U \).
\[ \faktor{{\mathrm{V}_\lambda}^\kappa}{U} = \qty{[f] \mid f : \kappa \to \mathrm{V}_\lambda} \]
The membership relation on the ultrapower is given by
\[ [f] \mathrel{E} [g] \leftrightarrow \qty{\alpha \mid f(\alpha) \in g(\alpha)} \in U \]
We have an embedding \( \ell \) from \( \mathrm{V}_\lambda \) into the ultrapower by mapping \( x \in \mathrm{V}_\lambda \) to the equivalence class of its constant function \( c_x : \kappa \to \mathrm{V}_\lambda \).
This is an elementary embedding by \L{}o\'s' theorem.
Hence
\[ \qty(\mathrm{V}_\lambda, \in) \equiv \qty(\faktor{{\mathrm{V}_\lambda}^\kappa}{U}) \]
so they both model \( \mathsf{ZFC} + \mathsf{MC} \), and in particular, \( [c_{\kappa}] \) is a measurable cardinal.
\begin{remark}
\begin{enumerate}
\item Suppose \( \faktor{{\mathrm{V}_\lambda}^\kappa}{U} \vDash [f] \text{ is an ordinal} \).
By \L{}o\'s' theorem,
\[ X = \qty{\alpha \mid f(\alpha) \text{ is an ordinal}} \in U \]
We can define
\[ f'(\alpha) = \begin{cases}
f(\alpha) & \text{if } \alpha \in X \\
0 & \text{otherwise}
\end{cases} \]
Note that \( f \sim f' \), so \( [f] = [f'] \).
So without loss of generality, we can assume \( f \) is a function into \( \mathrm{Ord} \cap \lambda = \lambda \), so \( f : \kappa \to \lambda \).
Since \( \lambda \) is inaccessible, \( f \) cannot be cofinal, so there is \( \gamma < \lambda \) such that \( f : \kappa \to \gamma \).
Note also that, for example, we can define \( f + 1 \) by
\[ (f + 1)(\alpha) = f(\alpha) + 1 \]
so
\[ \qty{\alpha \mid (f+1)(\alpha) \text{ is the successor of } f(\alpha)} = \kappa \in U \]
hence by \L{}o\'s' theorem, \( [f + 1] \) is the successor of \( [f] \).
\item If \( f : \kappa \to \mathrm{V}_\lambda \) is arbitrary, the set
\[ \qty{\rank f(\alpha) \mid \alpha \in \kappa} \]
cannot be cofinal in \( \lambda \), so there is \( \gamma < \lambda \) such that \( f \in \mathrm{V}_\gamma \).
However, the equivalence class \( [f] \) is unbounded in \( \mathrm{V}_\lambda \).
\item Given \( f \), by (ii) we may assume \( f \in \mathrm{V}_\gamma \) for some \( \gamma < \lambda \).
If \( [g] \mathrel{E} [f] \), then
\[ X = \qty{\alpha \mid g(\alpha) \in f(\alpha)} \in U \]
Now we can define
\[ g'(\alpha) = \begin{cases}
g(\alpha) & \text{if } \alpha \in X \\
0 & \text{otherwise}
\end{cases} \]
Then \( g \sim g' \) so \( [g] = [g'] \), and \( g' \in \mathrm{V}_\gamma \).
Therefore,
\[ \abs{\qty{[g] \mid [g] \mathrel{E} [f]}} \leq \abs{\mathrm{V}_\gamma} < \lambda \]
\end{enumerate}
\end{remark}
\begin{lemma}
\( \faktor{{\mathrm{V}_\lambda}^\kappa}{U} \) is \( E \)-well-founded.
\end{lemma}
\begin{proof}
Suppose not, so let \( \qty{[f_n] \mid n \in \mathbb N} \) be a strictly decreasing sequence, so
\[ [f_{n+1}] \mathrel{E} [f_n] \]
By definition,
\[ X_n = \qty{\alpha \mid f_{n+1}(\alpha) \in f_n(\alpha)} \in U \]
But as \( U \) is \( \kappa \)-complete,
\[ \bigcap_{n \in \mathbb N} X_n \in U \]
In particular, there must be an element \( \alpha \in \bigcap_{n \in \mathbb N} X_n \).
Hence, \( f_n(\alpha) \) is an \( \in \)-decreasing sequence in \( \mathrm{V}_\lambda \), which is a contradiction.
\end{proof}
Note that we only used \( \aleph_1 \)-completeness of \( U \).

We can take the Mostowski collapse to produce a transitive set \( M \) such that
\[ \pi : \qty(\faktor{{\mathrm{V}_\lambda}^\kappa}{U}, E) \cong (M, \in) \]
Combining \( \ell \) and \( \pi \), we obtain
\[ j = \pi \circ \ell : (\mathrm{V}_\lambda, \in) \to (M, \in) \]
given by
\[ j(x) = \pi(\ell(x)) = \pi([c_x]) \]
For convenience, will write \( (f) \) to abbreviate \( \pi([f]) \), so \( j(x) = (c_x) \).
\begin{lemma}
\( M \subseteq \mathrm{V}_\lambda \).
\end{lemma}
\begin{proof}
Note that because \( \lambda \) is inaccessible, \( \mathrm{V}_\lambda = \mathrm{H}_\lambda \), where
\[ \mathrm{H}_\lambda = \qty{x \mid \abs{\operatorname{tcl}(x)} < \lambda} \]
Since \( M \) is transitive, if \( \abs{x} < \lambda \) for each \( x \in M \), then \( M \subseteq \mathrm{H}_\lambda \).
But remark (iii) above shows precisely what is required.
\end{proof}
\begin{lemma}
\( \mathrm{Ord} \cap M = \lambda \).
\end{lemma}
\begin{proof}
Under the elementary embedding \( j \), ordinals in \( \mathrm{V}_\lambda \) are mapped to ordinals in \( M \).
So \( j \) restricts to an order-preserving embedding from \( \lambda \) into a subset of \( \lambda \).
Thus this embedding is unbounded, and therefore by transitivity, \( \mathrm{Ord} \cap M = \lambda \).
\end{proof}
\begin{lemma}
\( \eval{j}_{\mathrm{V}_\kappa} = \id \), so in particular, \( \mathrm{V}_\kappa \subseteq M \).
\end{lemma}
\begin{proof}
We show this by \( \in \)-induction on \( \mathrm{V}_\kappa \).
Suppose that \( x \in \mathrm{V}_\kappa \) is such that for all \( y \in x \), \( j(y) = y \).
For any \( y \in x \), by elementarity, \( j(y) \in j(x) \), but \( j(y) = y \) so \( y \in j(x) \) as required.
For the converse, suppose \( y \in j(x) \).
Then define \( f \) such that \( y = (f) \), so \( (f) \in (c_x) \).
Hence
\[ X = \qty{\alpha \mid f(\alpha) \in c_x(\alpha)} = \qty{\alpha \mid f(\alpha) \in x} \in U \]
But
\[ \qty{\alpha \mid f(\alpha) \in x} = \bigcup_{z \in x} \qty{\alpha \mid f(\alpha) = z} \]
This is a union of \( \abs{x} \)-many sets.
By \( \kappa \)-completeness, there must be some \( z \in x \) such that
\[ \qty{\alpha \mid f(\alpha) = z} \in U \]
Hence \( f \sim c_z \).
Therefore, \( (f) = j(z) \), and by the inductive hypothesis, \( j(z) = z \).
Hence \( y \in x \).
\end{proof}

0 comments on commit 987b2fe

Please sign in to comment.